Understanding Public Forum Debate

The following PDFs are great resources for understanding Public Forum Debate.

Public Forum: Advice for Debaters and Judges

Posted in Learn, Public-Forum | Comments Off on Understanding Public Forum Debate

Common LD Values

EQUALITY

Equality generally refers to  the idea that people are or ought to be the same in terms of political, economic, legal, or cultural status.  Equality has a close connection with morality and justice, since most theories of distributive justice recognize the importance of equality, and egalitarianism is the moral doctrine that people should be treated as equals. The fundamental ethical argument of equality is that there is no morally relevant distinction between people, so everyone deserves equal moral consideration. Stoics hold equality to mean that people are equally entitled to human worth, regardless of one’s nation, ethnicity, or gender. Modern secular cosmopolitans, such as Matha Nussbaum, also hold this view. This view also forms the basis of much of Kant’s work.  Similarly, Christian egalitarianism says that all human persons are equal in fundamental worth or moral status based on the notion that humankind were created in the living image of God and that God loves all human beings equally. (Although Christianity is far from the only religion advocating the notion of equal human worth.) It most commonly appears as a political ideal after its usage in the French Revolution. The United States Declaration of Independence includes moral and legal egalitarianism in the phrase “all men are created equal,” which implies that each person is to be treated equally under the law. Culturally, egalitarian theories have gained prominence in the past 200 years, and many caste-oriented or otherwise heavily classist societies have recently come under fire. Doctrines adovcating racial supremacy and ethnic destiny have been increasingly isolated and radicalized. Rigid and restrictive gender norms are being rearticulated in dynamic ways, and women’s rights can no longer be ignored. Egalitarian ideals have been politically accepted in the past two hundred years in the form of the socialism, communism, anarchism, democracy, and human rights movements, which promote various degrees of economic, political, and legal egalitarianism. Nietzsche argues against equality, because the presence of egalitarian values tends to thwart the flourishing of truly extraordinary individuals (extemely gifted artists, very intelligent scientists, those who transcend some social mores, etc.).

JUSTICE

Aristotle defined justice in his Ethics as giving each man what he is due.  The source of justice has been attributed to divine command, natural law, or human creation. Distributive justice involves maximizing benefit to the worst off. This theory of justice can be closely related to egalitarianism, such as in socialism. In this sense, distributive justice might conflict with property rights and other liberties. It should be noted that distributive justice, in other contexts, can mean maximizing aggrogate social welfare. In matters of criminal justice, this sense of distributive justice would advocate punishing the criminal if and only if such would deter future such crimes. On the other hand, retributive justice regards the proper response to wrong-doing as that which proportionately punishes the wrong-doing. Retributive justice says that impunity is almost always unjust.

SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORIES

Social contract describes the implied agreement by which people form nations and maintain a social order. Social contract theory maintains that the authority of the government must always derive from the consent of the governed.  Here, moral norms are established not from a perfectionist ideal of human nature or divine will but instead from the contract agreed upon by those that govern and those that are governed.  Government only as a contract in which people conditionally transfer some of their rights to the government in order to better ensure the more stabile enjoyment of their lives, liberty, and property.  Common to all of social contract theories is the notion of a sovereign will which all members of a society are bound by the social contract to respect.  Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, and Jean-Jacques Rousseau are the most famous philosophers of social contract theory.

CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE

The categorical imperative is the central philosophical concept of the moral philosophy of Kant, and of modern deontological ethics.  Kant  recognized the need for a system of “pure morality,” one that was truly rational and did not interject personal or subjective adulterants. The categorical imperative acts as a test to determine whether an action is moral, regrdless of who is acting. The categorical imperative is an absolute, unconditional requirementfor moral conduct. It is best known in its first formulation: “Act only according to that maxim whereby you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law.” This resembles the golden rule (Do only that which you would wish upon yourself.), but is slightly different. Kant’s central focus is rationality. It distinguishes humans form mere beasts, and gives us access to pure morality. When Kant says “you can at the same time will,” he has in mind a rational will. If the behaivior is universalized, and still rationally acceptable, then it is moral. It is not moral to specific people or cultures, because this determination comes from the rational will. If one rational person accepts an action by the categorical imperative, then Kant would say that everyone would accept that action as moral, since everyone is equally rational. Thus, the categorical imperative differs from the golden rule, because the golden rule allows for non-rational considerations. The categorical imperative attempts to identify what is inherent to morality, and it holds that rationality is the only way to know the moral. Since we’re all equally rational, we can all come to the same rational conclusions about moral behaivior. Nietzsche sharply disagrees with this notion.

DEONTOLOGY

Deontology is the theory of duty or moral obligation derived from Kant’s categorical imperative.  Deontologists argue the rightness or wrongness of an action does not depend on the goodness or badness of its consequences, as consequentialists believe.  The most famous deontological theory is that of Kant. In his theory, Kant claimed that various actions are morally wrong if they are inconsistent with the status of a person as a free and rational being, and that only those acts that further the status of people as free and rational beings are morally right. Therefore, Kant concluded that we all have an absolute duty to avoid acts that treat people as a means to some other end and to perform acts that affirm the rationally autonomous individual. This framework can be more strategic, because it makes it much harder for your opponent to outweigh you. If an action violates deontological constraints (in Nozick’s terms, “side-constraints”), the action is irredemably unjust. Your opponent cannot claim that you violate some other deontological principle and outweigh you, so long as you’ve established that your opponent has the positive burden to prove that thier side is actively consistent with justice.

UTILITARIANISM

Utilitarianism is the consequentialist ethical doctrine that the moral worth of an action is determined solely by its contribution to overall utility, which can be defined broadly as happiness or pleasure.  Jeremy Bentham is generally credited with the development of utilitarianism.  Bentham believed that pain and pleasure were the only intrinsic values in the world and thus derived the rule of utility, that the good is whatever brings the greatest happiness to the greatest number of people.  He influenced John Stuart Mill, who wrote in his On Liberty that utilitarianism is beneficial for politics and requires that political arrangements satisfy the “liberty principle” which states that “the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others.”

Posted in Learn, Lincoln-Douglas | Comments Off on Common LD Values

Understanding the Value-Criterion

By David Weeks

David was a high school debater in Louisianna and Texas and won 2nd place at the Tournament of Champions (TOC) in 2006.  He is currently a senior at Swarthmore College.

The Function of the Criterion

The value criterion (also known as a “standard”) is probably the most important individual part of any LD case. Above all, the value criterion is a “weighing standard” for arguments. That is, it is the lens that the judge sees arguments through. If the accepted criterion in the round is the protection of life, arguments about protecting privacy rights don’t matter. Judges often use the criterion as a “filter” for arguments, in that arguments whose impacts don’t pertain to the criterion are ignored. In this way, you should choose a value criterion that allows the judge to evaluate arguments in terms of it. That means your criterion will often be [verb + object], such as protecting life, minimizing suffering, rejecting violence, encouraging participation, etc.

If the judge cannot evaluate both your and your opponents’ arguments with your criterion, then it is likely a bad choice, because you aren’t telling the judge how to adjudicate clash between yours and your opponents’ arguments. This is not to say that you can’t have a strategic value criterion, or that you can’t frame the round to your advantage. Certainly, both of these are good ideas. However, this does mean that your opponent should be able to make arguments as to why their side could achieve your criterion. If there is no conceivable argument that your opponent can make as to why their side achieves your criterion, then you have most likely gone too far and made your criterion very unfair. On the other hand, if your opponent can make only make a few unconvincing or easily-outweighed arguments as to why their side achieves your value criterion, then you might have a promising criterion.

It is important to note that, if you chose to have a value premise, you must explain why the value criterion “achieves” your value premise. Different kinds of criteria go about this in different ways, so we’ll return to this later. Keep in mind that a value criterion is not a good criterion just because it achieves the value. Many novice often make the mistake of assuming that anything that might lead to or be consistent with the value premise is a good criterion. In many cases, this assumption leads to very boring, very annoying-to-judge criterion debates. So in the future, remember that the primary concern is to offer the judge a means of evaluating both sides’ arguments.

“Achieving the Criterion”

Many debaters throw around the rhetoric of “achieving the criterion” without any substantial explanation. There are several ways of achieving your value premise with your criterion, and you should understand how they all work.

The concepts of necessary and sufficient are useful here. Necessary is what is required. If x is necessary for y, then you cannot have y without x. An engine is necessary for a car. No engine, no (functioning) car. However, you don’t automatically have a car just because you have an engine. An engine is not sufficient for a car; you also need brakes, a steering wheel, etc. Thus, an engine is necessary, but insufficient for a car. When x is sufficient for y, then x achieves the entirety of y. For example, if you need a to use a pen, stealing a pen would be sufficient in order to attain a pen. However, you could also borrow or buy one from someone else.  If something is both necessary and sufficient, then it is the one and only thing that can achieve the entire value premise. If x is necessary and sufficient for y, then y is true if and only if x is true.  Usually, your value criterion aims to be both necessary and sufficient, but there are a few exceptions.

Remember that necessary, sufficient criteria can be difficult to develop, because devising a three-word phrase that describes everything that justice or morality could mean is impossible. This is why you must consider the criterion as a weighing mechanism, and not simply as a logical conduit leading to your value. You must consider the context of the resolution and common arguments from the other side. Think about what scenarios best represent the conflict between aff and neg, and devise your criteria with these conflict scenarios and common arguments in mind. Your criterion should be necessary and sufficient for your value premise, but in terms of the specifics of the resolution.

While the necessary sufficient structure is most common, some situations might leave room for a necessary, insufficient criterion. Some negatives use a necessary, insufficient standard in a clever way. The negative would accept the affirmative’s value premise while reading the negative case, and make arguments as to why the negative criterion is necessary, but insufficient to achieve the value premise. You may ask yourself, “why would it be strategic to intentionally make my criterion insufficient?” The answer is that, if you’re negative, you can force the affirmative to jump through two hoops: they have to achieve your criterion, since yours is necessary to the value. However, because your criterion is insufficient, the affirmative must also win their own criterion, since winning yours would not be enough to achieve the value. In this way, a necessary insufficient standard can be strategic because it forces the other side to prove that they fulfill two criteria, as opposed to just one. (Keep in mind that, for this strategy to work, you probably need to prove that negatives only need to deny the truth of the resolution in order to win, rather than win a counter-advocacy with pro-active reasons to negate.)

Necessary insufficient standards can be used in some affirmatives as well.  For instance, say the resolution is “Gun control laws are unjust.” The affirmative could say that the negative has the burden to prove that gun control is just, and that the affirmative merely has to demonstrate any form of injustice in gun control laws. By shifting the positive burden of proof to the negative side, the affirmative can offer multiple necessary insufficient criteria, and claim that the negative must meet all of the criteria, since each serves as an indicator of a specific level of injustice.  You can easily see why this might get out of hand, since a debater can impose seven necessary insufficient criteria upon the other side, which would be next to impossible.  Absolutely avoid using more than three standards, since many judges have becomes disgruntled with this trend. Also, be prepared to answer arguments about why multiple insufficient criteria is unfair because each side should have reciprocal burdens.

It is possible to have multiple criteria that function differently. With the necessary insufficient criteria, making your opponent lose one of the criteria will likely make them lose the round. You can also have multiple criteria that allow reciprocal burdens. For example, you could have three criteria, and whichever side that wins two or more of them wins. You can also have dual criteria, as long as you tell the judge what to do if each of you wins impacts to only one criterion.

A final consideration in formulating your value criterion is whether it is a maximization or “brightline” criterion. Some criteria, such as maximizing utility or minimizing suffering, do not proscribe how far to go. That is, there is no absolute threshold of suffering that you’d want to stay above under the “minimizing suffering” criterion; all that matters is that your side contributes to less suffering than your opponent’s side. A brightline criterion, on the other hand, establishes some specific threshold for when something is good or bad. Agency or side-constraint-related arguments are good examples of this. They say that there are certain non-negotiable things that the government cannot morally do, regardless of the benefits that might follow. For example, slavery might or might not have increased the south’s agricultural productivity before the Civil War, but we consider slavery unjust regardless of the benefits or harms. With brightline criteria, you don’t try to meet the criterion better than your opponent; you either simply meet the criterion, or you don’t. With maximization criteria, weighing impacts is critically important.

Posted in Learn, Lincoln-Douglas | Comments Off on Understanding the Value-Criterion

Guide to Popular Philosophers

by David Weeks

SOCRATES (470-399 BC)

  • Ancient Greek philosopher, credited for the development of the foundations of the Western philosophical tradition.
  • He forced his students to question their beliefs and problems and develop their own solutions by using a dialectic method of inquiry. (later known as the Socratic Method)
  • His most famous student was Plato, although he resisted being called a teacher, and refused to take money for what he did.
  • He refused the label teacher, because he believed that he did not transmit knowledge to passive listeners. Instead, by asking questions that lead people to realize their own ignorance, he represented a new approach.

PLATO (427-347 BC)

  • In his early writings, Plato conveyed the spirit of Socrates’ teaching by presenting reports of his master’s conversational interactions, providing us with our only accounts of Socrates’ thought.
  • Explained the difference between Forms and Ideas. He argued that Ideas (e.g., justice or beauty) and Forms are different the many objects that we can observe that are called beautiful or just. This bifurcation made possible a distinction between body and soul.
  • Plato’s most famous work remains the Republic.
  • Here, Plato tries to construct the perfect city, based upon justice and successful in teaching the virtues to its citizens
  • Plato concludes that such a perfect city exists only in speech
  • Socrates speaks out against democracy, favoring aristocracy

ARISTOTLE (384-322 BC)

  • Student of Plato
  • Although the surviving works of Aristotle probably represent only a fragment of the whole, they include his investigations of an amazing range of subjects, from logic, philosophy, and ethics to physics, biology, psychology, politics, and rhetoric.
  • Argued that moral conduct contributes to the good life for humans, most famously in his Ethics. Shifts emphasis from justice.
  • Here, he discusses the natural desire to achieve happiness, describes the operation of human volition and moral deliberation, develops a theory of each virtue as the mean between radical extremes, discusses the value of three distinct kinds of friendship, and defends his conception of an ideal life of intellectual pursuit.
  • In his Politics, Aristotle contends that the lives of individual human beings are invariably linked together in a social context and attempts to find the best state.
  • Argues that politics is important for men but not the highest science-only if men were the highest beings would politics be the highest science. Instead, metaphysics is, for Aristotle, most important.
  • Rejects Plato’s claims in the Republic and argues that monarchy is the best system of government.

AUGUSTINE (354-430 AD)

  • Born as the Roman Empire was crumbling.
  • Converted to Christianity after studying with Ambrose.
  • Develops a refined system of linguistics, and reinterprets the concept of sign. Disagrees with Stoic semiotics
  • Argues against the Skeptic group of philosophers that genuine human knowledge can be established with certainty by saying, “If I am mistaken, I exist.”
  • In De Civitate Dei (The City of God), Augustine distinguishes religion and morality from politics.
  • Claims that everything that we call evil must be good on some level, or it could not exist at all. There is no pure manifestation of absolute evil. It is evil because its disorder and misdirection cause it to “fail to attain all the goodness appropriate to it.” Since no absolute evil exists, there must be different levels of order and disorder, and different degrees of happiness, justice, and culpability.

AQUINAS (1224-1274)

  • Joined the Dominican order while studying philosophy and theology at Naples.
  • Wrote extensive commentaries on Aristotle’s works.
  • Summa Theologica represents the most complete summation of his thought.
  • Encompasses thousands of pages of tightly-reasoned responses to a wide range of questions about church theology and doctrine.
  • Attempts to prove that theology is superior to philosophy as theology concerns itself with knowledge that has been revealed by God and that man must accept on faith, while philosophy is concerned with only the knowledge that man acquires through sensory experience and the use of the natural light of reason.
  • He elaborates this kind of “practical reason,” and claims that it is only possible if people are autonomous and exercise free choice.
  • Articulates the distinction between is and ought.
  • Delineates distributive and commutative justice.
  • Aquinas holds that people naturally seek knowledge of that which is their true goal and happiness, that is, the vision of God.

MACHIAVELLI (1469-1527)

  • Began as a politician in Florence.
  • Wrote The Prince in order to gain favor with the Medicis, the ruling family of Florence at the time. He writes The Discourses in solitude, so some suggest that The Discourses better reflect his actual beliefs.
  • The Prince is an intensely practical guide to the exercise of raw political power over a Renaissance principality.
  • Focuses on practical success by any means, even at the expense of traditional morals and values. For him, the highest goal of a leader is to earn a glorious legacy and to be judged well by history.
  • Argues that it is primarily the skill of the individual leader, rather than his character, that determines the success of any state. Here, he acknowledges that the common good of the state should be the immediate concern of leaders, and generally denounces those who mar social well-being.

HOBBES (1588-1679)

  • Devoted much of his life to the development and expression of a comprehensive philosophical vision of the mechanistic operation of nature.
  • Lived during the bloody English Civil War, during which he wrote the Leviathan as the most complete expression of his philosophy.
  • Is very suspicious of history because it is divisive. After all, historical claims of lineage fueled the English Civil War.
  • Begins with physics, claiming that the natural state of objects is disorder and chaos.
  • Transitions to a materialistic account of human nature and knowledge, a deterministic account of human volition, and a pessimistic vision of the consequently natural state of human beings in perpetual struggle against each other that results in a life that is “solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short.” In other words, people will fight over scarce resources, so the state of nature is a state of war.
  • In the state of nature, there is no justice because there is no common arbitrator. Justice only has meaning when there is a common adjudicator.
  • Because the state of nature is so terrible, people contract into a government. The government can do whatever it needs to maintain order. Your resistance against the state is never legitimate, unless it wishes to intentionally kill you.

LOCKE (1632-1704)

  • Adopted an empiricist approach by arguing that all of our ideas-simple or complex-are ultimately derived from experience.
  • Believed that proper application of our cognitive capacities is enough to guide man’s action in the practical conduct of life.
  • His Second Treatise of Government offers a systematic account of the foundations of political obligation.
  • Says that the state of nature is not that bad, but people are bad at being impartial when judging their own cases, so the state is necessary to mediate disputes.
  • Contends that all rights begin in the individual property interest created by an investment of labor. Our labor is an extension of our body, so the products of our labor (our property) must be protected.
  • The social structure or commonwealth depends on the express consent of those who are governed by its political powers for its formation and maintenance.
  • There are natural rights which no commonwealth may infringe upon, such as life, liberty, and property. These are god-given, so no mortal may violate them.
  • Dissatisfied citizens reserve a lasting right to revolution. Absolute or arbitrary power must always be rejected, because they re-create the original state of nature.

ROUSSEAU (1712-1778)

  • Decried the effects of modern civilization because he believed that the pursuit of the arts and sciences promoted idleness and that the resulting political inequality encouraged alienation.
  • Disagrees with Hobbes’s notion of human nature. Claims that pity and revulsion to suffering, rather than egoism and self-interest, are primary.
  • Maintained that every variety of injustice found in human society is an artificial result of the control exercised by defective political and intellectual influences over the healthy natural impulses of otherwise noble savages. The state of nature isn’t that bad, and his age, with its rampant appropriation and slavery, was worse.
  • Explicated an alternative in On the Social Contract as a civil society voluntarily formed by its citizens and wholly governed by the general will expressed in their unanimous consent to authority. Emphasizes active participation based upon a notion of positive freedom, rather than simple non-coercion.
  • Once the general will is decisive, people cannot legitimately resist it. Even goes farther than Hobbes, because the state can legitimately kill you if the general will says so.

KANT (1724-1804)

  • Developed the most comprehensive and influential philosophical program of the modern era.
  • His central thesis-that the possibility of human knowledge presupposes the active participation of the human mind-is deceptively simple, but the details of its application are quite complex.
  • The categorical imperative is the central philosophical concept of the moral philosophy of Kant, and of modern deontological ethics.
  • Morality can be summed up in one, ultimate commandment of reason, or imperative, from which all duties and obligations derive called the categorical imperative. The C.I. allows us to know an objective and pure morality, rather than a code of ethics that’s colored by emotion and passion. Claims that a pure moral paradigm is purely rational.
  • Describes the categorical imperative as an absolute, unconditional requirement that exerts its authority in all circumstances.
  • Best known in its first formulation: “Act only according to that maxim whereby you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law.” This is different from the golden rule because of “will“. For Kant, rational autonomy separates animals from humans. Rationality, as the unique human trait, is how we formulate our will. For him, everyone is equally capable of rationality, so everyone would arrive at the same moral conclusions, if only we could remove our personal passions from moral deliberation. The C.I. is his way of doing this. In this way, the C.I. differs from the golden rule, because the golden rule permits non-rational considerations.

MARX (1818-1883)

  • Above all else, Marx believed that philosophy ought to be employed in practice to change the world.
  • Argued that the conditions of modern industrial societies invariably result in the estrangement of workers from their own labor. Structural and institutional arrangements trump human agency and the individual.
  • Partnered with Friedrich Engels to write the Communist Manifesto with the hope of precipitating social revolution. His other writings are more academic. While Das Capital is his longest, the Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts of 1844 are more debate-friendly.
  • Describes the class struggle between proletariat and bourgeoisie, distinguishes communism from other socialist movements, proposes a list of specific social reforms, and urges all workers to unite in revolution against existing regimes that prop up the bourgeoisie.
  • Capitalism is undesirable, because, while more efficient, it alienates us on several levels. We are alienated from the things that we produce, our “species being” (our “human nature”), and from other people. Claims that taking pride in labor, rather than rationally deliberating, is the uniquely human feeling. Capitalism takes this away because capitalist production is very repetitive; we cannot choose to go be a fisherman if we all work in a factory for 14 hours a day.
  • Claimed that communism was the last stage of a long economic history. He says advanced industrial capitalism must happen before a communist revolution. The Mao, Lenin, and Stalin rejected Marx on this point.

NIETZSCHE (1844-1900)

  • Wrote critiques of religion, morality, contemporary culture, philosophy, and science.
  • Famously put forward the idea that “God is dead”, and this death may result in radical perspectivism or may lead one to confront the fact that humans have always regarded truth perspectivally. Basically he’s saying that we have to either embrace radical nihilism (or at least a gloomy relativism), or we must confront the fact that there is no absolute truth. He favors confronting the lack of absolute truth, and so Nietzsche is NOT A NIHILIST. He actually spends the first chapter of Will to Power talking about with European nihilism is bad.
  • Claims that knowledge is an invention, in the sense that pieces of knowledge, fact, or Truth are not objective or universally true. Knowledge is invented at a particular time, by particular people. For example, the Kantian notion that people are rational creatures is an invention inspired by Kant’s observations about the world around him. He says we should confront the lack of objective truth by examining the history of the invention of particular pieces of knowledge. He calls this genealogy.
  • Applies genealogy to moral philosophy. Distinguished between master and slave moralities, the former arising from a celebration of life, the latter the result of ressentiment* at those capable of the former. This distinction becomes in summary the difference between “good and bad” on the one hand, and “good and evil” on the other; importantly, the “good” man of the master morality equates to the “evil” man of the slave morality. In other words, slave morality claims that being weak is good, and that being strong is evil. In his genealogy of justice, he claims that justice describes the state’s violent repression of ressentiment. This makes him an opponent of social contract theory.
  • Examined the “will to power” and eternal recurrence theories, in which living things are not just driven by the mere need to stay alive, but in fact by a greater need to wield and use power, to grow, to expend their strength, and, possibly, to subsume other “wills” in the process. This will manifests itself in a desire to make one’s invented knowledge seem fixed, objective, and eternal.

*Ressentiment is not the same as resentment, because ressentiment expresses not only a dislike for the conditions that made one weak and vulnerable, but a self-hatred for being weak. Consequently, we can interpret slave morality as a way to cope with ressentiment. The weak need a way to feel better about themselves, so they call the strong evil and say that being weak is a voluntary act of goodness.

FOUCAULT (1926-1984)

  • Prominent historian and psychologist, but the political influence of his work cannot be underestimated. Famous structuralist (and later, post-structuralist).
  • Uses genealogy. Like Nietzsche, he tries to show that a given system of thought emerges from contingent historical circumstances, instead of some rationally inevitable historical formula.
  • Acknowledges that knowledge is an invention, but brings focus to how these inventions become accepted. Claims that power and knowledge are inextricably linked.
  • Unlike Nietzsche, Foucault avoids genealogy of concepts like morality and justice in the abstract. He prefers to examine practices and institutions like sexuality, the prison, and the mental clinic. His account of the nature of power derives from his analysis of prisons. Claims that prisons represent the way that modern government make us submit because they rely on using surveillance to change the way we behave. Just like a prison security camera, we are not certain that a guard is watching the screen at the other end, but the notion that someone could always be watching us transforms our behavior. We have internalized our subordination and exercise it on each other. Everyone is watching everyone else.
  • This differs profoundly from how pre-modern systems of power worked, wherein physical force and restraint motivate compliance. Modern systems rely on surveillance and behavior modification.

RAWLS (1921-2002)

  • Advocates a political liberalism under an egalitarian economic arrangement. Concerned with distributive justice.
  • Argues that the state must be stable and legitimate, which require that citizens are reasonable and that those affected by a policy can influence it.
  • A Theory of Justice is his most famous work, where he articulates justice as fairness, in that each citizen should have access to the same basic liberties. Any social inequities should be open to the conditions of equal opportunity, and must not be bad for society’s least well-off.
  • Uses the veil of ignorance. We can use the veil of ignorance to understand what’s unfair. To apply it, you would ask what you would like society to look like, assuming that you know nothing about race, ethnicity, gender, age, income, wealth, natural endowments, comprehensive doctrine, etc. of any of the citizens in society. In this situation, it would be safest to assume you’re least advantaged, so you would seek to raise the minimum social safety net. This principle of maximizing the minimum level of well-being (ie. Raising the minimum standard for one’s quality of life) is called maximin reasoning. Under the veil of ignorance, they do know basic facts about human society, such as resource scarcity and the fact there are multiple conceptions of the good life.
  • Values tolerance between society and says that toleration is the basis of international society. He says that human rights should be the limits of this toleration, and that liberal societies ought to reject ideologies and governments that malign human rights.

NOZICK (1938-2002)

  • Wrote Anarchy, State, and Utopia in response to Rawl’s A Theory of Justice. Nozick rejects Rawl’s defense of redistributing wealth and defends free-market liberalism.
  • Emphasizes the Kantian notion that people ought not be used as a means to another end. People are ends in themselves. As such, there are certain “side-constraints” on what the government may do. Side-constraints are absolute, so violating them is never morally acceptable. He also borrows from the Lockean idea of self-ownership. We own ourselves and the fruits of our labor, and taking our property is a violation of a side-constraint.
  • He applies the logic of self-ownership to conclude that the welfare state constitutes a kind of forced labor. He claims that you must labor to earn money, and that the amount of money forcibly taken from you in the form of taxes constitutes a kind of slave labor. Taxes that are used to redistribute wealth mean that every citizen is a partial owner of you, since they have a partial property right in part of you, ie. in your labor that earned the money that was taxed and later given to them.
  • He says the only morally justifiable state is a minimal state that only protects people with the police and military, from fraud, theft, and violence. The state should also have a court system. The state cannot legitimately regulate what people consume, read, or talk about. Public education, welfare systems, and healthcare systems are immoral.

LEVINAS (1906-1995)

  • Explores the meaning of intersubjectivity. Says he studies ethics, but he is really studying how we relate to other people on a core level. He is very interested with the “face-to-face” encounter with a stranger.
  • Says that when we feel a connection to people because we realize they’re like us. We feel a sense of commonality with the stranger we walk by along the street, even if we have not talked to each other. This sense of commonality and relatedness give us a natural aversion to human suffering. We feel the emergence of an obligation when we see raw human suffering. This is why we feel revulsion when we see the terrified Darfurian child or the hungry stranger.
  • Ethics begins with a responsibility to the Other. We feel this responsibility, regardless of whether or not a particular other ahs reciprocated this responsibility. The roots of ‘intersubjecivity’ lie in this immediate sense of connection to the Other. We feel a universal fraternity with the other that spawns an obligation. He finds the origins of language here, in the desire to respond to the other. Thus, “first philosophy” for Levinas, starts from an interpretative phenomenology and the face-to-face encounter with the other rather than God or the world.

LYOTARD (1924-1998)

  • French philosopher and literary theorist. His most famous work is The Post-Modern Condition
  • He claims that the post-modern era is characterized by a disbelief in metanarratives, or totalizing explanations of the way the world works. Liberalism, Marxism, etc. are totalizing ideologies in that they assert that certain principles are always true, such as the progress of history, the verifiability of everything by science, and the possibility of absolute freedom. He claims that we have stopped believing that these narratives can explain, represent, and contain us all. We now understand that there are different world paradigms, as so postmodernity is characterized by many micronarratives rather than metanarratives.
  • Uses the idea of “phrase regimens”, or communities of meaning and the separate systems in which those meanings are produced. It seems that ethics would be impossible if we did not subscribe to any metanarrative, since justice and injustice would only operate in terms of specific “phrase regimens”. In Le Différend, he develops a sense of post-modern justice, explaining that the most flagrant act of injustice would be to use the language rules from one phrase regimen and apply them to another. Ethics is about paying attention to things in their particularity and not enclosing them within arbitrary concepts.

 

DERRIDA (1930-2004)

  • Described as the “founder of deconstruction”
  • Claims that justice can never be completely achieved. It is a horizon towards which we aspire, but we never quite get there. Justice can never be equated with law.
  • Argues that every case is unique and there is no freedom in mindlessly applying rules, so justice can never be achieved because justice is recalculated constantly.
  • Justice is an analytic tool that we can use to critique the status quo and demand improvement. Rosa Parks acted illegally, and claimed that the law did not meet the demands and aspiration of justice.
  • We can never give someone “their due” because this would require knowing “the entire horizon of knowledge”.

David was a successful high school LD debater earning 2nd place at the 2006 TOC.  He is currently a senior at Swarthmore College.

 

Posted in Lincoln-Douglas | Comments Off on Guide to Popular Philosophers

April PF Topic Overview

Resolved: The United States federal government should permit the use of financial incentives to encourage organ donation.

Introduction

This topic will give you a nice break from the legal topics NFL has used for the past several months. The idea of offering financial incentives to increase organ donation has been around for quite a while. Although many of you may think that this topic has come out of left field, it is actually something the health community has been grappling with for decades.

The National Organ Transplant Act, passed in 1984, forbids citizens from selling their organs. It says specifically that people cannot exchange human organs “for valuable consideration.” However, states regularly offer tax breaks for organ donors.

This topic may have a tendency to devolve into emotional, sensitive debates. The affirmative may make the case that children are dying world over due to a shortage of donor organs, and the negative may make the case that the poor will be taken advantage of by those seeking a quick liver. Try to avoid using emotional language when you make your arguments so that you can focus on clash.

The definition of “financial incentives” will most likely become a huge part of the debate. The affirmative will have the burden of defining financial incentives; although, the negative can present an alternate definition if they disagree with the affirmative’s definition. You may think that the definition of financial incentive is pretty straightforward – money in exchange for organs. But actually, it’s a lot deeper than that. Financial incentives have been proposed that come in the form of health insurance premium discounts for those that sign up to be organ donors, helping the family of the deceased with funeral expenses if they donate their loved one’s organs, and offers to defray medical costs.

The affirmative probably has an upper hand in this debate. Given the intense amount of calls for creative ways to increase organ donations, the affirmative will generally have more material with which to work. The negative will probably have to do some creative research into the ethics of organ donation.

Affirmative

First, the affirmative can press the need for an increase in organ donations. An editorial in USA Today reads, “More than 6,000 patients die each year while on waiting lists. Demanding patience, when the price of delay is death, is no answer. It’s time to try new ideas.”[i]

To put the issue into perspective, “Over the years, the number of people waiting for an organ in the U.S. has soared upward, increasing from 31,000 people in 1993 to over 101,000 today.”

Millions of people suffer from kidney disease, but in 2007 there were just 64,606 kidney-transplant operations in the entire world. In the U.S. alone, 83,000 people wait on the official kidney-transplant list. But just 16,500 people received a kidney transplant in 2008, while almost 5,000 died waiting for one.[ii]

Affirmative debaters can argue that financial incentives will dramatically increase the availability of organs and decrease the price. Consider these examples in Singapore, Iran and Israel.[iii]

  • Singapore is preparing to pay donors as much as 50,000 Singapore dollars (almost US$36,000) for their organs.
  • Iran has eliminated waiting lists for kidneys entirely by paying its citizens to donate.
  • Israel is implementing a “no give, no take” system that puts people who opt out of the donor system at the bottom of the transplant waiting list should they ever need an organ.

The Iranian system and the black market demonstrate one important fact: The organ shortage can be solved by paying living donors.[iv] The Iranian system began in 1988 and eliminated the shortage of kidneys by 1999.

While affirmative debaters can defend financial incentives in general, they can also offer a specific proposal. Nobel Laureate economist Gary Becker and Julio Elias estimated that a payment of $15,000 for living donors would alleviate the shortage of kidneys in the United States. Payment could be made by the federal government. Moreover, this proposal would save the government money since even with a significant payment, transplant is cheaper than the dialysis that is now paid for by Medicare’s End Stage Renal Disease program.

Next, it is important that the affirmative preclude the arguments the negative will likely make regarding the manipulation of the poor. G. van Dijk and Dr. M.T. Hilhorst argue that financial incentives don’t have to mean cash at all, and that our system can ensure that people are not manipulated. They say, “Our regulated system is also able to guarantee that the voluntary nature of the act is not compromised. Under these conditions, payment can be a strong encouragement to this form of donation, which is becoming increasingly important. Life-long exemption from health insurance premiums is the most suitable method in this case. It would show how committed the government is to reducing the organ deficit, demonstrate that the effort of donors is highly appreciated, and that the government is prepared to cover any health risks.”

Further, the affirmative can argue that the negative’s assertion that the poor will be manipulated is problematic. Peter A. Clark says, “to deny financial incentives for fear of exploiting low income individuals and minorities implies that they are incapable of making voluntary decisions. Prohibiting low income people from receiving financial incentives for donating their organs for fear of abuses doesn’t really help them, it just leaves them poor. With the proper educational safeguards in place and with government regulation of the financial incentives for donation the informed consent of all people would be protected.”[v]

Additionally, the affirmative can propose a system where the donors would be compensated, and their organs would go into a donor bank to be doled out to those in need – like it is now. But, instead of waiting on goodwill to be the motivating factor for organ donation, it becomes the much more convincing incentive of money. This way, the rich are unable to buy up organs while the poor wait.

Negative

Some topics lend themselves to “counterplan” NCs, meaning that the negative would offer alternatives to the prescribed affirmative advocacy. On this topic, the 1NC would offer alternatives to financial incentives for organ donations. This allows the negative to agree that we need more organ donors. The negative agrees this is a problem but just offer a different solution. For example, the 1NC could advocate putting people higher up on the waiting list should they ever need an organ if they donate—an incentive, just not a financial one. [vi]

This might be a system of “presumed consent.” In this system, you are automatically assumed to be an organ donor upon your death unless you opt out of the system. Spain and Belgium already have this system in place, and Britain is heavily considering such a policy. According to the British Medical Journal (BMJ), Spain currently has the highest rate of organ donation in the world at 35.1 donors per million population. The BMJ says, “over a decade the number of transplant coordinator teams increased from 25 to 139. This combination of a system of presumed consent, which portrays a positive attitude towards donation, major financial investment, and good organization, seems to be the way forward.”[vii]

Additionally, the negative can argue for a system that gives organ preference to those that are declared organ donors. Right now, the system operates on who needs the organ the most. This might seem like the right thing to do, it provides no incentive for people to become organ donors. A system that gave preference to organ donors instead might provide more incentive for people to sign up. David J. Undis, speaking at a Cato Institute policy forum titled “Remedying the Organ Shortage: The Ethics of Market Incentives,” said, “There is a simple, effective, ethical, and already legal way to reduce the organ shortage in America and make the organ allocation system fairer in the process. You can donate your organs to people who will do the same for you. You can tell everyone: ‘If you don’t agree to donate your organs when you die, then you will go to the back of the transplant waiting list if you ever need one of my organs to live. When it’s time to decide who gets my organs, I am putting organ donors first.'” He said that LifeSharers is a non-profit organization that is doing just that. Members agree to donate their organs to other members when they die.[viii] In fact, Israel has already instituted this system in order to increase their low rate of organ donors. They continue to keep those who need organs the most at the top of the list, but when patients who are more or less equal in need are up for an organ, those who are already donors are given preference.[ix]

The negative should keep in mind that they have no obligation to provide an alternative to solving the problem of organ donation shortages. They can instead refute the affirmative case point by point and make a number of arguments.

First, the negative can argue that the ability to pay for organs decreases the dignity of the donor. The National Kidney Foundation is adamantly opposed to financial incentives for organ donation. They say, “Offering direct or indirect economic benefits in exchange for organ donation is inconsistent with our values as a society. Any attempt to assign a monetary value to the human body, or body parts, either arbitrarily, or through market forces, diminishes human dignity. By treating the body as property, in the hope of increasing organ supply, we risk devaluating the very human life we seek to save.”

The National Kidney Foundation maintains that offering financial incentives devalues the gift of life that donors have provided out of altruism, and leave out families who are unable to donate organs but consent to tissue donation

Second, the negative can argue that people would not be motivated by financial incentives any way. The National Kidney Foundation reports, “In a recent survey of families who refused to donate organs of their loved ones who have died, 92 percent said that payment would not have persuaded them to donate. Public opinion polls and focus groups have disclosed that many Americans are not inclined to be organ donors because they distrust the U. S. health care system, in general, and, in particular, because they are concerned that the health care of potential organ donors might be compromised if their donor status were known.”

So, if financial incentives will not increase the amount of donors, why embark on what promises to be a costly, unethical venture? The negative can argue that the costs of offering financial incentives will not be outweighed by lives saved.

Finally, the negative can argue that financial incentives exploit the poor. Dr. Francis L. Delmonico, a transplant surgeon and medical director of the New England Organ Bank in Newton, Massachusetts says, “Once you insert monetary gain into the equation of organ donation, now you have a market. Once you have a market, markets are not controllable; markets are not something you can regulate. The problem with markets is that rich people would descend upon poor people to buy their organs, and the poor don’t have any choice about it.”


[i] “Organ donations fall short; financial incentives can help,” USA Today, June 25, 2006. http://www.usatoday.com/news/opinion/editorials/2006-06-25-our-view_x.htm

[ii]John Goodman, “What We Can Learn from Iran about Organ Donation,” Health Policy Blog, National Center for Policy Analysis, April 13, 2010. http://healthblog.ncpathinktank.org/what-we-can-learn-from-iran-about-organ-donation/

[iii] Alex Tabarrok, “The Meat Market,” Wall Street Journal, January 8, 2010. http://online.wsj.com/article/SB10001424052748703481004574646233272990474.html

[iv] John Goodman, “What We Can Learn from Iran about Organ Donation,” Health Policy Blog, National Center for Policy Analysis, April 13, 2010.

http://healthblog.ncpathinktank.org/what-we-can-learn-from-iran-about-organ-donation/

[v] Financial Incentives For Cadaveric Organ Donation: An Ethical Analysis. By: Clark, Peter A. Clark, Internet Journal of Law, Healthcare & Ethics, 15288250, 2006, Vol. 4, Issue 1

[vi] “Financial incentives for organ donation: An investigation of the ethical issues,” by G. van Dijk Dr. M.T. Hilhorst. The Hague: Centre for Ethics and Health, 2007.

http://www.ceg.nl/data/file/Orgaandonatie_huisstijl_eng_def.pdf

[vii] “Is presumed consent the answer to organ shortages? Yes.” By Veronica English, British Medical Journal. May 24, 2007. http://www.bmj.com/content/334/7603/1088.full

[viii] “Putting Organ Donors First,” David J. Undis, May 13, 2004. http://www.wellsphere.com/general-medicine-article/putting-organ-donors-first/726644

[ix] “Israeli organ donors to get transplant priority,” BBC News, Dec. 17, 2009. http://news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/8416443.stm

Posted in Uncategorized | Comments Off on April PF Topic Overview

UIL Spring Topic Overview

by Christopher Burk, Director of Debate at the University of Texas at Dallas

Resolved: Free trade should be valued above protectionism.

In today’s globalized world, trade is an integral part of most every country’s economy.  According to the World Trade Organization (WTO), in 2008, $19.5 trillion dollars worth of merchandise and commercial services were traded.   Many support the expansion of free trade and seek to reduce trade barriers such as quotas, tariffs, and domestic subsidies. Proponents of free trade often argue that trade leads to economic growth and a high quality of living.  However, others warn of the dangers of free trade and advocate for protectionism which typically takes the form of tariffs and subsidies. A tariff is a tax levied on an imported good in order to make that good relatively more expensive than a domestically produced good to protect that industry. A subsidy is another form of protectionism in which the government gives special tax breaks or credits in order to support a company or industry competing against foreign companies.  The motivations for protectionism are varied, but most are aimed at helping domestically produced goods flourish by making it more expensive, harder or impossible to buy foreign imports of the same or similar products.

Currently, nearly every country practices some form of protectionism. Milton Friedman explained that tariffs are the “rule” for the currently global economy. He said, “The only major exceptions are nearly a century of free trade in Great Britain after the repeal of the Corn Laws in 1846, thirty years of free trade in Japan after the Meiji Restoration, and free trade in Hong Kong under British rule.” So, while the amount of protectionism may vary from country to country, it is accepted that virtually country practices some form of protectionism.

Value Criterion Discussion

The value you choose for this resolution will probably be different from any other that you have encountered thus far this season. Many debaters use justice as their default value but will be unable to do so on this topic. It will be too difficult to adequately defend “justice” as your value for this topic.

Instead, focus on values such as societal welfare, freedom and government legitimacy. Societal welfare serves either side well. It simply enforces the idea that either type of trade policy will be better for society. Government legitimacy can support either side as well.  Freedom is obviously better suited for free trade, and basic arguments for this value can be morphed to fit the global scale of this resolution.

Other values that focus on societal good, progress, and can be applied globally will also work. Be creative, but make sure that your value can be applied easily, without having to waste too much time explaining the connection between your value and the resolution. One reminder that bears emphasis is that the affirmative cannot value “free trade” and the negative cannot value “protectionism.” Values are meant to be overarching goods that both sides have the capability of reaching. If the affirmative values “free trade,” it would be impossible for the negative to achieve that value. This eliminates clash in the round.  For more on understanding values read our paper “Understanding the Value Criterion” here: http://debate-central.ncpathinktank.org/research/understanding-the-value-criterion  

The criterion should be very specific to your case. For instance, if you are arguing that free trade is beneficial because the principle of comparative advantage allows the world economy to flourish, then your criterion might be simply “the principle of comparative advantage.” Alternatively, if you argue that free trade is good because it increases competition, then your criterion might be “increase in global competition.” On the other hand, if you are arguing the protectionism is good because it allows countries to preference other countries that treat workers fairly, your criterion could be “the protection of human rights.”

Criteria can be detailed and varied. Especially for this resolution, please ignore the lists of “common criteria” that you have stashed somewhere in your debate rom. These will most likely not be helpful, and will prevent you from developing a strong criterion. As always, when in doubt, you can email your case or questions to us and we will review them and give you feedback!

Affirmative

There are many arguments available to affirmative debaters. 

First, free trade generates economic growth. International trade benefits the world economy as a whole.  It allows people, regions and nations to specialize in the production of what they do best, to enjoy the economies of large-scale production and to buy more cheaply those things that others do best.  We explore why below. 

Comparative Advantage.  One way that trade contributes to an increase in economic output is through comparative advantage, which creates more value with the same resources.  The Heritage Foundation explains comparative advantage by describing a situation in which one person can only use the goods which he or she produced. Obviously the person would produce some goods well and others poorly. Alternatively, that person could spend his or her time producing the one good he or she produces best and then sell it for a profit to others. The person could use the profit to buy goods from others that produce other goods best and at the lowest cost. This would arguably increase quality of living by allowing people to produce the best goods at the lowest prices.

The Heritage Foundation explains further: “It simply makes sense for each person to work at what he or she does best and to buy the rest. As a nation, the United States exports in order to purchase imports that other nations produce more skillfully and cheaply. Therefore, the fewer barriers erected against trade with other nations, the more access people will have to the best, least expensive goods and services in the world ‘supermarket.'” (You can find more here: http://www.heritage.org/research/reports/2004/05/why-america-needs-to-support-free-trade )

If a country were to instead place tariffs on goods that other countries produced cheaper to increase the chance that goods produced domestically were bought, they would be forcing their citizens to buy products for a more expensive price, and perhaps products that aren’t as good. 

Competition. Free trade increases competition between different firms in different countries.  This in turn stimulates a real cost reduction for producers when they compete with other producers, which increases economic efficiency.  This works because it shocks lazy firms into a serious search for ways to reduce real costs.  When they are protected by ample tariff and nontariff barriers, firms tend to pursue a comfortable way of life. Competition from the world marketplace can shock owners and managers, making them work harder to reduce real costs than they would under the umbrella of protection.  

Rather than fearing competition as many protectionist advocates do, affirmatives can argue that competition through free trade benefits all by promoting innovation and efficiency.  By spurring countries and companies to innovate to create better products and produce them in less costly ways, economic competition fuels the innovation needed to increase economic growth and wealth.  For more on this topic read NCPA publication “Trade and Economic Growth I” here: http://www.ncpathinktank.org/pub/ba552 and “Trade and Economic Growth II” here: http://www.ncpathinktank.org/pub/ba553.  

Economists Jeffery Sachs and Andrew Warner examined trade policies of 117 countries over 20 years and found a strong, positive correlation between free trade and growth. In fact, growth was three to six times higher in open economies than in closed ones. Free trade has been behind the booming growth and reduction in poverty in numerous developing countries. Affirmatives can argue that free trades empowers poor people with greater opportunities to create wealth and support their families, free trade and open markets disperse economic power and increase the living standards of all.

In 2000, the WTO found that the poor benefit greatly from trade liberalization reporting that, “Trade liberalization is generally a strongly positive contributor to poverty alleviation-it allows people to exploit their productive potential, assists economic growth, curtails arbitrary policy interventions and helps to insulate against shocks.”[i]

Steven Horowitz agrees that developing countries can be lifted from poverty through free trade. He believes that they can use comparative advantage to do so. He says: “For many Third World countries, their comparative advantage is the cheapness of their labor and the availability of some natural resources. For Western firms, this presents an opportunity for profit by reducing labor and resource costs. When Western firms open up shop in the Third World, they bring capital to those places. This creates jobs for citizen there and provides the West with cheaper goods. It is the classic mutual benefit of all exchange: the developing country gets jobs; the home country gets cheaper goods.”[ii]

Protectionism in the form of farm subsidies can be devastating to developing countries in Africa because farming accounts for nearly 70 percent of total employment and is the main source of income for the majority of Africans living in poverty. For example, more than 10 million Africans depend directly on cotton production. Since the 1990s, world cotton prices have fallen by half, much of which is due to U.S. farm subsidies, according to the International Cotton Advisory Committee. Their estimates suggest that world cotton prices would rise by 26 percent if the United States repealed cotton subsidies. This amounts to an increase of over $300 million per year in income for African cotton farmers.

Second, the affirmative can make the claim that free trade decreases the likelihood of war and increases peace. In 1748, Baron de Montesquieu wrote that “Peace is the natural effect of trade. Two nations who differ with each other become reciprocally dependent; for if one has an interest in buying, the other has an interest in selling; and thus their union is founded on their mutual necessities.”

This can be a powerful affirmative argument.   If the United States is dependent on, say, China for trade, we may be deterred from starting a war with China because, in the end, we need the goods they give us more than we need to blow them up. Likewise, if China is dependent on the money we give them for the things they provide, they will be less likely to take extreme action in the case of a disagreement.

Donald J. Boudreaux says that if free trade “promotes peace, then protectionism – a retreat from open trade – raises the chances of war.” He provides several empirical examples to support this including two major studies on the relation between trade and peace.

The first is a study done by Solomon Polachek, an economist at the State University of New York at Binghamton and co-author Carlos Seiglie of Rutgers University. They find “overwhelming evidence that trade reduces conflict.” They find the same for foreign investment: the greater foreigners invest in the United States or the more Americans invest abroad, the lower the chances of war between those countries and the United States. Professors Polachek and Seiglie conclude that, “The policy implication of our finding is that further international cooperation in reducing barriers to both trade and capital flows can promote a more peaceful world.”

The second is a study by Columbia University political scientist Erik Gartzke. Gartzke places countries on an economic-freedom index from 1 to 10 (1 is very unfree and 10 is very free). He then compares them to military conflicts from 1816 to 2000. He found that countries that countries with scores of 2 or less are 14 times more likely to be involved in military conflict than those countries that rank at 8 or higher. Gartzke concluded that, “When measures of both economic freedom and democracy are included in a statistical study, economic freedom is about 50 times more effective than democracy in diminishing violent conflict.”[iii]

Beyond economics, free trade has important moral and democratic implications. Affirmatives can argue that by its very nature, free trade limits the power of the centralized state and gives more freedom and autonomy to the individual. Protectionism, the Cato Institute writes, “is a form of stealing.”  Free trade on the other hand gives to each person control over what is his or her own.  Affirmatives can claim that this allows people to fulfill their creative and productive potential. Moving beyond the individual, free trade fosters relationships and exchange that goes beyond economics. Not only material goods are exchanged, but also people, ideas, technology, religion, and friendship are fostered. Even John Keynes was of the opinion that free trade could promote world peace by fostering interdependent relationships among nations.  Free trade also has an important influence on the spread of democratic values. By promoting the rule of law necessary for international trade transactions, free trade actually promotes democratic values of decentralized economic power, individual sovereignty and freedom. Rule of law brought about by honest and open free trade reduces the influence of corruption and bribery. Free trade reduces the incentives for corruption by promoting economic growth and improving wages and standards of living. Additionally, the ideas of democracy and individual liberty are disseminated through trade as borders are open to not only goods but also to information, ideas, and values.

Negative

Negative debaters can make numerous arguments on this topic.

First, the negative can argue that allowing comparative advantage to flourish without constraints can lead to national security problems. Specialization, while it can be beneficial, also has some important and dangerous consequences if free trade is promoted in the entire economy. Negatives can note that some industries are of a unique and vital national interest and protecting them allows for economic diversity and security for the public good. Proponents of protectionism often cite the agricultural and heavy industrial sectors such as steel as vital economic sectors for security.  The United States, for instance, might stop farming and instead import all food from a couple countries. What happens if we go to war with one or both of those countries?

In addition to being a vital industry, agriculture has important cultural significance. A country may want to maintain a domestic food supply for the sake of security as well as preserving agricultural interests and farmer’s lifestyles. Agriculture also has a unique exposure to price fluctuations as environmental factors can have major impacts on prices. As vital interest, agricultural products are often shielded from foreign competition. In the European Union, for example, agricultural subsidies compose over 47 percent of the EU’s budget. 

Another vital industry is heavy industry such as the production of steel and coal. In the event of war, it is vital for a country to have the ability to produce steel and other resources for military manufacturing. If a country did not protect this vital industry and other countries produced the steel needed, it would be at the whim of other countries in a matter of vital national security. For these reasons, negatives can argue that protecting vital industries is justified.   

Second, negatives can argue that it is necessary to protect the economies of developing countries.  The WTO promotes policies that allow countries to give preference to underdeveloped countries to encourage the growth of their economy. Negatives can argue that giving these countries preference over larger countries allows them to compete in the global market. 

A study done by the USDA’s Economic Research Service found that these preference provisions are helpful to developing countries. The study says: “Many countries rely heavily on these programs, as indicated by the sizable share of their exports that receive preferences. In 2002, more than 50 percent of agricultural exports of 21 countries entered the U.S. market under preferential programs.

The figure was even higher for the EU, where preferences covered over half of the agricultural exports from 49 countries.”[iv]

Next, the negative can point out that protectionist policies can be used to encourage good behavior. Many opponents of free trade argue that free trade creates a “wild west” world in which countries continually attempt to undercut each other at the expense of labor. Negatives can argue that free trade promoted by the WTO establishes a “race to the bottom” in wages by pitting workers against each other across the globe.  Rather than promoting internationally recognized labor standards, free trade undercuts wages and labor standards in pursuit of cheaper and more efficient labor. Low wages and minimal standards serve as a magnet for global investment as companies and firms seek to minimize labor costs in order to maximize profit margins. This argument, proponents maintain, can also be applied to environmental standards as companies are most attracted to those countries with minimal environmental standards. This also reduces the cost of business and can lead to higher profit margins sought by companies operating in a free trade world. These serious consequences of free trade on both labor and the environment are powerful arguments for the negative.[v]

Finally, the need to protect newly emerging industries is the basis for the infant industry argument against free trade. This argument maintains that in order to grow and compete in the future, new industries need temporary protection from foreign competition.  A critical need, this protectionism allows those industries to establish themselves in the key beginning stages shielded from foreign competition from established firms. Protection gives these industries and companies a chance to progress and develop a completive advantage in the future. Negatives can argue that if this protection is not given, new industries will never develop in a country as they are killed off by mature foreign competitors before they are even given a chance to take root. Protection in the form of tariffs for competitors or tax credits for companies would allow the government to establish and grow industries which would benefit the public good such as technology, solar, and green industries which have the potential to create millions of jobs. For emerging countries, this form of infant industry protection would allow less developed countries to start their own industries which can eventually compete on the global market alongside industries from developed countries.


[i] “Free trade helps reduce poverty, says new WTO secretariat study,” World Trade Organization, June 13, 2000. http://www.wto.org/english/news_e/pres00_e/pr181_e.htm

[ii] “Free trade and the climb out of poverty,” Steven Horowitz. http://www.fee.org/pdf/the-freeman/horwitz0305.pdf

[iii] “Want world peace? Support free trade.” Donald J. Boudreaux, The Christian Science Monitor. Nov. 20, 2006. http://www.csmonitor.com/2006/1120/p09s02-coop.html

[iv] “Agricultural Trade Preferences and the Developing Countries,” USDA Economic Research Service. http://www.ers.usda.gov/publications/err6/err6.pdf

[v] “EU gives developing countries duty-free access with GSP+,” Europa. Dec. 9, 2008. http://europa.eu/rapid/pressReleasesAction.do?reference=IP/08/1918&format=HTML&aged=1&language=EN&guiLanguage=e

Posted in Lincoln-Douglas | Comments Off on UIL Spring Topic Overview

Glossary of Key Terms

Space Terminology

As you are researching this topic you are likely to come across words that are new to you.  Below we have defined key terms you may come across as you begin to read about this topic.

Continue reading

Posted in Cross-Examination | Comments Off on Glossary of Key Terms